Two envelopes problem
Encyclopedia
The two envelopes problem, also known as the exchange paradox, is a brain teaser
Brain teaser
A brain teaser is a form of puzzle that requires thought to solve. It often requires thinking in unconventional ways with given constraints in mind; sometimes it also involves lateral thinking. Logic puzzles and riddles are specific types of brain teasers....

, puzzle
Puzzle
A puzzle is a problem or enigma that tests the ingenuity of the solver. In a basic puzzle, one is intended to put together pieces in a logical way in order to come up with the desired solution...

 or paradox
Paradox
Similar to Circular reasoning, A paradox is a seemingly true statement or group of statements that lead to a contradiction or a situation which seems to defy logic or intuition...

 in logic, philosophy, probability and recreational mathematics, of special interest in decision theory
Decision theory
Decision theory in economics, psychology, philosophy, mathematics, and statistics is concerned with identifying the values, uncertainties and other issues relevant in a given decision, its rationality, and the resulting optimal decision...

 and for the Bayesian interpretation
Bayesian probability
Bayesian probability is one of the different interpretations of the concept of probability and belongs to the category of evidential probabilities. The Bayesian interpretation of probability can be seen as an extension of logic that enables reasoning with propositions, whose truth or falsity is...

 of probability theory
Probability
Probability is ordinarily used to describe an attitude of mind towards some proposition of whose truth we arenot certain. The proposition of interest is usually of the form "Will a specific event occur?" The attitude of mind is of the form "How certain are we that the event will occur?" The...

. Historically, it arose as a variant of the necktie paradox
Necktie paradox
The necktie paradox is a puzzle or paradox within the subjectivistic interpretation of probability theory. It is a variation of the two-envelope paradox....

.

A statement of the problem starts with:
It is possible to give arguments that show that it will be to your advantage to swap envelopes by showing that your expected return on swapping exceeds the sum in your envelope. This leads to the logical absurdity that it is beneficial to continue to swap envelopes indefinitely.

A large number of different solutions have been proposed. The usual scenario is that one writer proposes a solution that solves the problem as stated, but then some other writer discovers that by altering the problem a little the paradox is brought back to life again. In this way a family of closely related formulations of the problem is created which are then discussed in the literature.

It is quite common for authors to claim that the solution to the problem is easy, even elementary. However, when investigating these elementary solutions they are not the same from one author to the next. Currently, at least a couple of new papers are published every year.

Problem

The basic setup: You are given two indistinguishable envelopes, each of which contains a positive sum of money. One envelope contains twice as much as the other. You may pick one envelope and keep whatever amount it contains. You pick one envelope at random but before you open it you are offered the possibility to take the other envelope instead.

The switching argument: Now suppose you reason as follows:
  1. I denote by A the amount in my selected envelope.
  2. The probability that A is the smaller amount is 1/2, and that it is the larger amount is also 1/2.
  3. The other envelope may contain either 2A or A/2.
  4. If A is the smaller amount the other envelope contains 2A.
  5. If A is the larger amount the other envelope contains A/2.
  6. Thus the other envelope contains 2A with probability 1/2 and A/2 with probability 1/2.
  7. So the expected value
    Expected value
    In probability theory, the expected value of a random variable is the weighted average of all possible values that this random variable can take on...

     of the money in the other envelope is



  8. This is greater than A, so I gain on average by swapping.
  9. After the switch, I can denote that content by B and reason in exactly the same manner as above.
  10. I will conclude that the most rational thing to do is to swap back again.
  11. To be rational, I will thus end up swapping envelopes indefinitely.
  12. As it seems more rational to open just any envelope than to swap indefinitely, we have a contradiction.


The puzzle: The puzzle is to find the flaw in the very compelling line of reasoning above.

First resolution

This follows from the recognition that the symbol A in step 7 is effectively used to denote two different quantities, committing the fallacy of equivocation
Equivocation
Equivocation is classified as both a formal and informal logical fallacy. It is the misleading use of a term with more than one meaning or sense...

. This error is brought into relief if we denote by X the smaller amount, making 2X the larger amount, then reconsider what happens in steps 4 and 5:

4. If A=X then the other envelope contains 2A (or 2X).

5. If A=2X then the other envelope contains A/2 (or X).

Each of these steps treats A as a random variable
Random variable
In probability and statistics, a random variable or stochastic variable is, roughly speaking, a variable whose value results from a measurement on some type of random process. Formally, it is a function from a probability space, typically to the real numbers, which is measurable functionmeasurable...

, assigning a different value to it in each possible case. However, step 7 continues to use A as if it is a fixed variable, still equal in every case. That is, in step 7, 2A is supposed to represent the amount in the envelope if A=2X, while A/2 is supposed to represent the value if A=X. However, we cannot continue using the same symbol A in one equation under these two incompatible assumptions. To do so is equivalent to assuming A=X=2X; which, for nonzero A, implies 1=2.

This resolution was first noted by Bruss and later explored in an exhaustive paper by Nickerson and Falk.

Second resolution

Blachman, Christensen and Utts (1996), and many later authors working in probability theory, pointed out that if the amounts of money in the two envelopes have any proper probability distribution, then it is simply impossible that whatever the amount A=a in the first envelope, it is equally likely that the second contains a/2 or 2a. Thus step 6 of the argument which leads to always switching is a non-sequitur.

In fact in order for step 6 to be true, whatever a might be, the smaller amount of money in the two envelopes must be equally likely to be between 1 and 2, as between 2 and 4, as between 4 and 8 ... and for that matter, as between 1/2 and 1, as between 1/4 and 1/2 ... But there is no way to divide total probability 1 into an infinite number of pieces which are both equal and larger than zero. Yet the smaller amount of money in the two envelopes must have probability larger than zero to be in at least one of the just mentioned ranges!

To see this, suppose that the chance that the smaller of the two envelopes contains an amount between and is , where n is any whole number, positive or negative, and for definiteness we include the lower limit but exclude the upper in each interval. It follows that the conditional probability that the envelope in our hands contains the smaller amount of money of the two, given that its contents are between and , is . If this is equal to 1/2, it follows by simple algebra that , or . This has to be true for all n, an impossibility.

Third variant

Though probability theory can defuse the original paradox, it turns out that examples can still easily be found of proper probability distributions, such that the expected value of the amount in the second envelope given that in the first does exceed the amount in the first, whatever it might be.

Denote again the amount of money in the first envelope by A and that in the second by B. We think of these as random. Let X be the smaller of the two amounts and Y=2X be the larger. Notice that once we have fixed a probability distribution for X then the joint probability distribution of A,B is fixed, since A,B = X,Y or Y,X each with probability 1/2, independently of X,Y.

The bad step 6 in the "always switching" argument led us to the finding for all a, and hence to the recommendation to switch, whether or not we know a. Now, it turns out that one can quite easily invent proper probability distributions for X, the smaller of the two amounts of money, such that this bad conclusion is still true! (One example is analysed in more detail below). It cannot be true that whatever a, given A=a, B is equally likely to be a/2 or 2a, but it true that whatever a, given A=a, B is larger in expected value than a.

Example

Here we present some details of a famous example due to John Broome
John Broome (philosopher)
John Broome is a British philosopher and economist. He is currently the White's Professor of Moral Philosophy at the University of Oxford and a Fellow of Corpus Christi College, Oxford....

 of a proper probability distribution of the amounts of money in the two envelopes, for which for all a.

Suppose that the envelope with the smaller amount actually contains 2n dollars with probability p(n)=2n/3n+1 where n = 0, 1, 2,… These probabilities sum to 1, hence the distribution is a proper prior (for subjectivists) and a completely decent probability law also for frequentists.

A sensible strategy is certainly to swap when the first envelope contains 1, as the other must then contain 2. Now suppose the first envelope contains 2. In this case there are only two possibilities; the envelope pair in front of us is either {1, 2} or {2, 4}. The probability the pair is {1,2} and the first envelope contains 2 is , and the probability the pair is {2,4} and the first envelope contains 2 is . Therefore the conditional probability
Conditional probability
In probability theory, the "conditional probability of A given B" is the probability of A if B is known to occur. It is commonly notated P, and sometimes P_B. P can be visualised as the probability of event A when the sample space is restricted to event B...

 that it's the {1, 2} pair given the first envelope contains 2 is


and consequently the probability it's the {2, 4} pair is 2/5 since all other envelope pairs have zero conditional probability.

It turns out that these proportions hold in general unless the first envelope contains 1. Thus, denote by x the amount found where x = 2n for some n ≥ 1, then the other envelope contains x/2 with probability 3/5 and 2x with probability 2/5. Note that except for the case that the first envelope contains 1, given the first envelope contains x, the second envelope is more likely to be smaller than larger, yet its conditionally expected amount is larger: the expected gain by switching is


which is more than x. This means that as far as expected values are concerned, the player should switch in all cases, yet as far as probabilities are concerned , he should not switch, unless he happens first of all to get an envelope containing 1.

Third resolution

Fortunately, the new paradox can be defused again. Suppose for all a. As remarked before, this is possible for some probability distributions of X (the smaller amount of money in the two envelopes). Averaging over a, it follows either that , or alternatively that . But A and B have the same probability distribution, and hence the same expectation value, by symmetry (each envelope is equally likely to be the smaller of the two). Thus both have infinite expectation values, and hence so must X too.

Thus if we switch for the second envelope because its conditional expected value is larger than what actually is in the first, whatever that might be, we are exchanging an unknown amount of money whose expectation value is infinite for another unknown amount of money with the same distribution and the same infinite expected value. Typically, the chance that the second envelope contains more money than the first decreases as the amount a in the first envelope gets larger and larger.

The average amount of money in both envelopes is infinite. Exchanging one for the other simply exchanges an average of infinity with an average of infinity. The larger the amount of money in the first envelope, the more likely this is the larger amount of the pair, even if the other has a larger expectation value given the specific quantity in the first.

These are the facts of life. And enough resolution of the paradox for those working in probability theory. Probability theory tells us why and when the paradox can occur and explains to us why it gives no cause for worry. In a real-life situation, the expectation of the amount of money in an envelope cannot be infinity, since the total amount of money in the world is bounded; therefore any probability distribution describing the real world would have to assign probability 0 to the amount being larger than the total amount of money on the world, so the expectation of the amount of money under this distribution cannot be infinity. The resolution of the second paradox is that the postulated probability distributions cannot arise in a real-life situation.

Non-probabilistic variant

The logician Raymond Smullyan
Raymond Smullyan
Raymond Merrill Smullyan is an American mathematician, concert pianist, logician, Taoist philosopher, and magician.Born in Far Rockaway, New York, his first career was stage magic. He then earned a BSc from the University of Chicago in 1955 and his Ph.D. from Princeton University in 1959...

 questioned if the paradox has anything to do with probabilities at all. He did this by expressing the problem in a way which doesn't involve probabilities. The following plainly logical arguments lead to conflicting conclusions:
  1. Let the amount in the envelope chosen by the player be A. By swapping, the player may gain A or lose A/2. So the potential gain is strictly greater than the potential loss.
  2. Let the amounts in the envelopes be Y and 2Y. Now by swapping, the player may gain Y or lose Y. So the potential gain is equal to the potential loss.
  3. Let the amount in the envelope not chosen by the player be B. By swapping, the player may gain B/2 or lose B. So the potential gain is strictly smaller than the potential loss.


(Actually Smullyan only mentioned arguments 1 and 2; argument 3 was added later, by James Chase, who was the first to publish a solution of the paradox, see below).

Solutions to Smullyan's non-probabilistic variant

A number of solutions have been put forward. Albers, Kooi, and Schaafsma (2005) consider that without adding probability (or other) ingredients to the problem, Smullyan's arguments do not give any reason to swap or not to swap, in any case. Thus there is no paradox. This dismissive attitude is common among writers from probability and economics: Smullyan's paradox arises precisely because he takes no account whatever of probability or utility.

Rather careful and often highly technical analyses have been made by many authors from the field of logic. Though solutions differ, they all pinpoint semantic issues concerned with counterfactual
Counterfactual thinking
Counterfactual thinking is a term of psychology that describes the tendency people have to imagine alternatives to reality. Humans are predisposed to think about how things could have turned out differently if only..., and also to imagine what if?....

 reasoning. We want to compare the amount that we would gain by switching if we would gain by switching, with the amount we would lose by switching if we would indeed lose by switching. However, we cannot both gain and lose by switching at the same time. We are asked to compare two incompatible situations. Only one of them can factually occur, the other will be a counterfactual situation, somehow imaginary. In order to compare them at all, we must somehow "align" the two situations, we must give them some definite points in common.

James Chase (2002), for instance, argues that the second argument is correct because it does correspond to the way to align two situations (one in which we gain, the other in which we lose) which is preferably indicated by the problem description. Also Bernard Katz and Doris Olin (2007) argue this point of view. It was James Chase, incidentally, who first added argument number 3 to the arguments 1 and 2 originally compared by Smullyan.

In the second argument, we consider the amounts of money in the two envelopes as being fixed; what varies is which one is first given to the player. Because that was an arbitrary and physical choice, the counterfactual world in which the player, counterfactually, got the other envelope to the one he was actually (factually) given is a highly meaningful counterfactual world and hence the comparison between gains and losses in the two worlds is meaningful. This comparison is uniquely indicated by the problem description, in which two amounts of money are put in the two envelopes first, and only after that is one chosen arbitrarily and given to the player. In the first argument, however, we consider the amount of money in the envelope first given to the player as fixed and consider the situations where the second envelope contains either half or twice that amount. This would only be a reasonable counterfactual world if in reality the envelopes had been filled as follows: first, some amount of money is placed in the specific envelope which will be given to the player; and secondly, by some arbitrary process, the other envelope is filled (arbitrarily or randomly) either with double or with half of that amount of money.

On the other hand Byeong-Uk Yi (2009) argues that comparing the amount you would gain if you would gain by switching with the amount you would lose if you would lose by switching is a meaningless exercise from the outset. According to his analysis, all three conclusions are false (or meaningless). He analyses Smullyan's arguments in detail, showing that intermediate steps are being taken, and pinpointing exactly where an incorrect inference is made.

Foundations of mathematical economics

In mathematical economics and the theory of utility, which explains economic behaviour in terms of expected utility, there remains a problem to be resolved. In the real world we presumably wouldn't indefinitely exchange one envelope for the other (and probability theory, as just discussed, explains quite well why calculations of conditional expectations might mislead us). Yet the expected utility based theory of economic behaviour says (or assumes) that people do in practice make economic decisions by maximizing expected utility, and hence predicts that people would switch indefinitely.

Fortunately for mathematical economics and the theory of utility, it is generally agreed that as an amount of money increases, its utility to the owner increases less and less, and ultimately there is a finite upper bound to the utility of all possible amounts of money. We can pretend that the amount of money in the whole world is as large as we like, yet the owner of all that money will not have more and more use of it, the more is in his possession. For decision theory and utility theory, the two envelope paradox illustrates that unbounded utility does not exist in the real world, so fortunately there is no need to build a decision theory which allows unbounded utility, let alone utility of infinite expectation.

Controversy among theoretical economists

As mentioned above, any distribution producing this variant of the paradox must have an infinite mean. So before the player opens an envelope the expected gain from switching is "∞ − ∞", which is not defined. In the words of Chalmers this is "just another example of a familiar phenomenon, the strange behaviour of infinity". Chalmers suggests that decision theory
Decision theory
Decision theory in economics, psychology, philosophy, mathematics, and statistics is concerned with identifying the values, uncertainties and other issues relevant in a given decision, its rationality, and the resulting optimal decision...

 generally breaks down when confronted with games having a diverging expectation, and compares it with the situation generated by the classical St. Petersburg paradox
St. Petersburg paradox
In economics, the St. Petersburg paradox is a paradox related to probability theory and decision theory. It is based on a particular lottery game that leads to a random variable with infinite expected value, i.e., infinite expected payoff, but would nevertheless be considered to be worth only a...

.

However, Clark and Shackel argue that this blaming it all on "the strange behaviour of infinity" doesn't resolve the paradox at all; neither in the single case nor the averaged case. They provide a simple example of a pair of random variables both having infinite mean but where one is always better to choose than the other. This is the best thing to do at every instant as well as on average, which shows that decision theory doesn't necessarily break down when confronted with infinite expectations.

Many mathematical economists are happy to exclude infinite expected utility by assumption, hence excluding the paradox altogether. Some try to generalise some of the existing theory to allow infinite expectations. They are stuck with the paradoxical example just given.

Extensions to the Problem

McDonnell and Abbott analyze a modified problem in which the player is allowed to look in the first envelope before deciding whether to switch or to stay.

They also allow the arranger of the game to decide which amount will be given to the player, with the smaller amount given with probability p and the larger amount with probability . Thus corresponds to the case when the player is given one of the two envelopes completely at random, as in the original problem.

In their analyses, McDonnell and Abbott represent the values in the two envelopes by two random variables. This could either express the subjective beliefs
Bayesian probability
Bayesian probability is one of the different interpretations of the concept of probability and belongs to the category of evidential probabilities. The Bayesian interpretation of probability can be seen as an extension of logic that enables reasoning with propositions, whose truth or falsity is...

 of the player concerning the unknown values in the two envelopes in just one play of the game, or it could express a frequentist model where we imagine the game played many times and the numbers in the envelopes being fixed by a physical randomization procedure. Either way, the lower amount of money X, is thought of as drawn from some probability distribution, and the second amount is then 2X.

In fact, there is no uniform probability distribution
Uniform distribution (continuous)
In probability theory and statistics, the continuous uniform distribution or rectangular distribution is a family of probability distributions such that for each member of the family, all intervals of the same length on the distribution's support are equally probable. The support is defined by...

 over all the real numbers. However, McDonnell and Abbott do work first formally with the situation that X is drawn from a uniform distribution over the interval and . This can be done, since in the Bayesian
Bayesian probability
Bayesian probability is one of the different interpretations of the concept of probability and belongs to the category of evidential probabilities. The Bayesian interpretation of probability can be seen as an extension of logic that enables reasoning with propositions, whose truth or falsity is...

 calculations, where one wants to condition
Conditional probability
In probability theory, the "conditional probability of A given B" is the probability of A if B is known to occur. It is commonly notated P, and sometimes P_B. P can be visualised as the probability of event A when the sample space is restricted to event B...

 on the observed value of the amount of money in one of the two envelopes, one only needs to know the prior density of X up to proportionality, so one can formally go through the usual calculations with a uniform prior density, even though there is no uniform prior distribution over the whole real line. This is one popular way to mathematically represent subjectivist total ignorance of the amounts of money in the two envelopes, but in Bayesian statistics
Bayesian statistics
Bayesian statistics is that subset of the entire field of statistics in which the evidence about the true state of the world is expressed in terms of degrees of belief or, more specifically, Bayesian probabilities...

 it is called an improper prior distribution, and it is well known that use of such non-normalizable prior densities can lead to incorrect deductions. Note that this prior distribution implies that for any number x, the player finds it infinitely more likely that the smaller amount of money is larger than x than that it is smaller than x! (In Bayesian statistics
Bayesian statistics
Bayesian statistics is that subset of the entire field of statistics in which the evidence about the true state of the world is expressed in terms of degrees of belief or, more specifically, Bayesian probabilities...

, the prior for a completely unknown positive number is actually conventionally more often taken as the improper prior density 1/x).

There is no constant switching strategy that will improve the player's expectations. However, in the case where , not surprisingly, the player can improve his expectation by always switching (when ) or never switching (when ).

A player can take advantage of different probability distributions for X, if he would know this distribution. If probability
Probability
Probability is ordinarily used to describe an attitude of mind towards some proposition of whose truth we arenot certain. The proposition of interest is usually of the form "Will a specific event occur?" The attitude of mind is of the form "How certain are we that the event will occur?" The...

 is taken in the subjectivist sense, then the distribution of X simply represents the player's initial beliefs as to the prior likelihood of different values of x, and so is known, by definition. As a practical matter, the arranger of the game will likely have a limit on the amount of money he can put in the envelopes. As such, he would likely limit the distribution of X to the range , where K is some fixed limit. In this case, it is also possible to increase our expectation by switching when we observe small amounts of money in the envelope and keeping the envelope when it contains a large amount. The threshold between "small" and "large" is subjective and can be fixed at different values, but it should be possible to take advantage of the fact that some of the larger values seen in the game can only be the 2X amount, as these are drawn from a larger domain over . It should thus be advantageous to keep the larger values when there is a greater likelihood that they come from the range .

Thinking of the arranger of the game and the player as two parties in a two person game, puts the problem into the range of game theory
Game theory
Game theory is a mathematical method for analyzing calculated circumstances, such as in games, where a person’s success is based upon the choices of others...

. The arranger's strategy consists of a choice of a probability distribution of X. The player's strategy consists of a probability of switching for each possible amount of money he sees in the envelope he opens. Obviously if the player knows the arranger's strategy, the probability distribution of X, then he can compute his optimal switch-or-stay strategy by application of Bayes' theorem
Bayes' theorem
In probability theory and applications, Bayes' theorem relates the conditional probabilities P and P. It is commonly used in science and engineering. The theorem is named for Thomas Bayes ....

. However, what if he doesn't know the arranger's strategy? This connection is further explored in the next section.

Randomized solutions

As mentioned before, McDonnell and Abbott consider the situation in which the player is allowed to look in the first envelope before deciding whether to switch or to stay. The player is allowed either to keep this amount, or to switch and take the amount of money in the other envelope, whatever it might be. Is it possible for the player to make his choice in such a way that he goes home with the larger amount of money with probability strictly greater than half?

We are given no information at all about the two amounts of money in the two envelopes, except that they are different, and that neither envelope is empty, in other words, both amounts of money are strictly greater than zero. In particular, we are not told the joint probability distribution of the two numbers. We are not asking for a subjectivist solution. We must think of the two numbers in the envelopes as chosen by the arranger of the game according to some possibly random procedure, completely unknown to us, and fixed. Think of each envelope as simply containing a positive number and such that the two numbers are not the same. The job of the player is to end up with the envelope with the larger number. This variant of the problem, as well as its solution, is attributed by McDonnell and Abbott to information theorist Thomas M. Cover
Thomas M. Cover
Thomas M. Cover is Professor jointly in the Departments of Electrical Engineering and Statistics at Stanford University...

.

Counter-intuitive though it might seem, there is a way that the player can decide whether to switch or to stay so that he has a larger chance than 1/2 of finishing with the bigger sum of money, however the two numbers are chosen by the arranger of the game. However, it is only possible with a so-called randomized algorithm
Randomized algorithm
A randomized algorithm is an algorithm which employs a degree of randomness as part of its logic. The algorithm typically uses uniformly random bits as an auxiliary input to guide its behavior, in the hope of achieving good performance in the "average case" over all possible choices of random bits...

, that means to say, the player needs himself to be able to generate random numbers
Statistical randomness
A numeric sequence is said to be statistically random when it contains no recognizable patterns or regularities; sequences such as the results of an ideal dice roll, or the digits of π exhibit statistical randomness....

. Suppose he is able to think up a random amount of money, let's call it Z, such that the probability that Z is larger than any particular quantity z is exp(-z). Note that exp(-z) starts off equal to 1 at z=0 and decreases strictly and continuously as z increases, tending to zero as z tends to infinity. So the chance is 0 that Z is exactly equal to any particular amount of money, and there is a positive probability that Z lies between any two particular different amounts of money. The player compares his Z with the amount of money in the envelope he is given first. If Z is smaller he keeps the envelope. If Z is larger he switches to the other envelope.

Think of the two amounts of money in the envelopes as fixed (though of course unknown to the player). Think of the player's random Z as a probe with which he decides whether the number in the first envelope is small or large. If it is small compared to Z he will switch, if it is large compared to Z he will stay.

If both amounts of money are smaller than the player's Z then his strategy does not help him, he ends up with the second envelope, which is equally likely to be the larger or the smaller of the two. If both amounts of money are larger than Z his strategy does not help him either, he ends up with the first envelope, which again is equally likely to be the larger or the smaller of the two. However if Z happens to be in between the two amounts, then his strategy leads him correctly to keep the first envelope if its contents are larger than those of the second, but to switch to the second if the first envelope has smaller contents than the second. Altogether, this means that he ends up with the envelope with the larger amount of money with probability strictly larger than 1/2. To be precise, the probability that he ends with the "winning envelope" is 1/2 + Prob(Z falls between the two amounts of money)/2.

In practice, the number Z we have described could be determined, to any required degree of accuracy, as follows. Toss a fair coin many times, and convert the sequence of heads and tails into a binary fraction: HTHHTH... becomes the binary representation 0.101101.. of some number y. Then Z = - ln (1-y). Note that we just need to toss the coin long enough that we can see for sure whether Z is smaller or larger than the number in the first envelope. So we only ever need to toss the coin a finite number of times.

The particular probability law (the so-called standard exponential distribution
Exponential distribution
In probability theory and statistics, the exponential distribution is a family of continuous probability distributions. It describes the time between events in a Poisson process, i.e...

) used to generate the random number Z in this problem is not crucial. Any continuous probability distribution
Probability distribution
In probability theory, a probability mass, probability density, or probability distribution is a function that describes the probability of a random variable taking certain values....

 over the positive real numbers which assigns positive probability to any interval of positive length will do the job.

This problem can be considered from the point of view of game theory
Game theory
Game theory is a mathematical method for analyzing calculated circumstances, such as in games, where a person’s success is based upon the choices of others...

, where we make the game a two-person zero-sum game with outcomes win or lose, depending on whether the player ends up with the lower or higher amount of money. One player chooses the joint distribution of the amounts of money in both envelopes, and the other player chooses the distribution of Z. The game does not have a "solution" (or saddle point) in the sense of game theory. This is an infinite game and von Neumann's minimax theorem does not apply.

History of the paradox

The envelope paradox dates back at least to 1953, when Belgian mathematician Maurice Kraitchik
Maurice Kraitchik
Maurice Kraitchik was a Belgian mathematician and populariser born in Minsk. His main interests were the theory of numbers and recreational mathematics.He is famous for having inspired the two envelopes problem in 1953, with the following puzzle in...

 proposed a puzzle in his book Recreational Mathematics
concerning two equally rich men who meet and compare their beautiful neckties, presents from their wives, wondering which tie actually cost more money. It is also mentioned in a 1953 book on elementary mathematics and mathematical puzzles by the mathematician John Edensor Littlewood
John Edensor Littlewood
John Edensor Littlewood was a British mathematician, best known for the results achieved in collaboration with G. H. Hardy.-Life:...

, who credited it to the physicist Erwin Schroedinger. Martin Gardner
Martin Gardner
Martin Gardner was an American mathematics and science writer specializing in recreational mathematics, but with interests encompassing micromagic, stage magic, literature , philosophy, scientific skepticism, and religion...

 popularized Kraitchik's puzzle in his 1982 book Aha! Gotcha, in the form of a wallet game:
Two people, equally rich, meet to compare the contents of their wallets. Each is ignorant of the contents of the two wallets. The game is as follows: whoever has the least money receives the contents of the wallet of the other (in the case where the amounts are equal, nothing happens). One of the two men can reason: "I have the amount A in my wallet. That's the maximum that I could lose. If I win (probability 0.5), the amount that I'll have in my possession at the end of the game will be more than 2A. Therefore the game is favourable to me." The other man can reason in exactly the same way. In fact, by symmetry, the game is fair. Where is the mistake in the reasoning of each man?


In 1988 and 1989, Barry Nalebuff
Barry Nalebuff
Barry Nalebuff is Milton Steinbach Professor of Management at Yale School of Management. He is an expert in business strategy and game theory, as well as many other topics.-Education:Graduated Highschool at Belmont Hill School...

 presented two different two-envelope problems, each with one envelope containing twice what's in the other, and each with computation of the expectation value 5A/4. The first paper just presents the two problems, the second paper discusses many solutions to both of them. The second of his two problems is the one which is nowadays the most common and which is presented in this article. Martin Gardner
Martin Gardner
Martin Gardner was an American mathematics and science writer specializing in recreational mathematics, but with interests encompassing micromagic, stage magic, literature , philosophy, scientific skepticism, and religion...

 independently mentioned this same version in his 1989 book Penrose Tiles to Trapdoor Ciphers and the Return of Dr Matrix. Since then, the paradox has been most commonly presented in the symmetric two-envelopes form: the two envelopes are filled first, then one is chosen at random, and called Envelope A. Barry Nalebuff's asymmetric variant, often known as the Ali Baba problem, has one envelope filled first, called Envelope A, and given to Ali. Then a coin is tossed to decide whether Envelope B should contain half or twice that amount, and then given to Baba.

See also

  • Bayesian probability
    Bayesian probability
    Bayesian probability is one of the different interpretations of the concept of probability and belongs to the category of evidential probabilities. The Bayesian interpretation of probability can be seen as an extension of logic that enables reasoning with propositions, whose truth or falsity is...

  • Bertrand's paradox
    Bertrand's paradox (probability)
    The Bertrand paradox is a problem within the classical interpretation of probability theory. Joseph Bertrand introduced it in his work Calcul des probabilités as an example to show that probabilities may not be well defined if the mechanism or method that produces the random variable is not...

  • Deal or No Deal
    Deal or No Deal
    Deal or No Deal is the name of several closely related television game shows, the first of which was the Dutch Miljoenenjacht produced by Dutch producer Endemol. It is played with up to 26 cases with certain sums of money...

  • Decision theory
    Decision theory
    Decision theory in economics, psychology, philosophy, mathematics, and statistics is concerned with identifying the values, uncertainties and other issues relevant in a given decision, its rationality, and the resulting optimal decision...

  • Double or nothing
    Double or nothing
    Double or nothing in a betting situation is where the loser of a bet gets another chance at the bet. When a "double or nothing" bet is requested by the loser, if the winner accepts, then they play again. If the loser of the initial bet loses again, then the winner gets double the original bet...

  • Monty Hall problem
  • Necktie paradox
    Necktie paradox
    The necktie paradox is a puzzle or paradox within the subjectivistic interpretation of probability theory. It is a variation of the two-envelope paradox....

  • Newcomb's paradox
    Newcomb's paradox
    Newcomb's paradox, also referred to as Newcomb's problem, is a thought experiment involving a game between two players, one of whom purports to be able to predict the future. Whether the problem is actually a paradox is disputed....

  • St. Petersburg paradox
    St. Petersburg paradox
    In economics, the St. Petersburg paradox is a paradox related to probability theory and decision theory. It is based on a particular lottery game that leads to a random variable with infinite expected value, i.e., infinite expected payoff, but would nevertheless be considered to be worth only a...

  • Two envelopes problem/sources
    Two envelopes problem/sources
    The following is a list of sources, ordered chronologically, that discuss the well-known two-envelope paradox.- 1982 :* Martin Gardner, Aha! Gotcha: Paradoxes to Puzzle and Delight, W.H. Freeman and Company, New York, p 106.- 1987 :...

The source of this article is wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.  The text of this article is licensed under the GFDL.
 
x
OK